First, it's not a property right in "their creations." It's a property right in other peoples' creations. It is claiming ownership over the fruits of the labor of others. It's important that we be clear about this.
Obviously everyone's creations build upon the blocks that came before (Newton's comment about standing on the shoulders of giants comes to mind), but nonetheless copyrighted works are original to their author. As Feist makes clear, without originality, there is no copyright.
Second, whatever your take on these "property rights," they are certainly not Lockean.
My views are Lockean in that I think it's proper for an author to get a property right in the fruits of their intellectual labor, as I said. I also said I subscribe to other schools of thought as well. I'm not a staunch Lockean such that I think copyright is innate, must be perpetual, and there must not be fair use. I don't know what innate means, but I do think the idea of giving the author (and no one else) the property right is fair. Perhaps that's innate in some sense. I wouldn't mind if copyright were perpetual, but I accept that there's more going on than the author and I think the balance permitted by fair use and limited terms is also fair and serves countervailing interests.
In light of these two restrictions, it's really hard to see how Locke's theory of property should apply to copyright at all. Combine this with the unquestionable ethical wrongs that result in a Lockean "property view" of copyright, and I can say with confidence that holding this view is immoral.
But it does show that if you're going to justify treating copyright as a "property right," it has to be for reasons that are not Locke's. You have to find some other way of showing how they are "fair."
I told you my view is simple. I think it's fair that authors should get a property right in their writings. That's exactly what it says in the Copyright Clause, so that makes me happy.
You do more than this. You say that copyright is entirely unlike other restrictions on speech. For example, you directly claimed that infringing speech is no more "speech" than prostitution. You claimed this specifically to justify protected speech being blocked. You have advocated this even before fair use or idea/expression determinations could be made. You have advocated this even when links to infringing speech result in the blocking of actual non-infringing speech.
I think we'd have to run through those arguments again. Sounds like you're referring to Arcara, where the Court rejected an argument that prostitution is imbued with enough protective speech/conduct to warrant heightened First Amendment scrutiny. I can't remember exactly what our disagreement was there, but I do remember thinking that you were making a circular argument.
Regardless, the case law and commentary has many references to how copyright is not a restriction on speech, as "copyright laws, of course, protect only the form of expression and not the ideas expressed." New York Times v. United States, 403 U.S. 713, 726, n.* (1971) (Brennan, J., concurring). The reason is because copyright doesn't lock up ideas, which is the evil that the First Amendment addresses.
Yet if you think anyone is even suggesting that protecting free speech justifies infringing on the "property right" of copyright holders, you claim they're "piracy apologists" who "just want stuff for free." You have never even considered that they might be defending free speech rights. You have never even considered that the right to free speech might justify allowing infringement, even temporarily. I'm betting that even reading these sentences makes you angry.
Not at all. I think I'd need a concrete example though, as it's hard for me to see it in the abstract.
You clearly think that copyright is vastly more important than free speech. This makes your opinion on whether "the inhibition is great" highly questionable, to say the least.
The First Amendment is more important, which is why copyright laws get First Amendment scrutiny. I have no problem with that, and I think the tests created by the Court are great.
And let's not forget that free speech rights are not the only rights that are in conflict with copyright. Holding a copyright means nothing other than that you have an ownership interest in the property of others. For the sake of argument, let's take the Lockean view of property. Copyright says that if I apply my own labor, using resources that I paid for, I do not own the fruits of that labor. At least, not if my fruits taste too much like yours.
I disagree with the premise that copyright means having an ownership interest in the property of others. And I don't really understand you. Copyright says you get a property right in the fruits of your labor, so long as you create something original (not novel, but original; I think you're mixing the two).
Being a monopoly, it's also a restraint on free trade. I don't know if you consider free trade any kind of "right," but at the very least, monopolies are not ethical.
If I write a book, I don't corner the entire book market. I have a monopoly over my book. That's not really a monopoly in the sense that I learned the word in macroeconomics. If my rights in my book are a monopoly, then all private property is a monopoly of sorts.
Theft is not immoral because it "infringes on a property right." It is immoral because it deprives the owner of the use of that property. If someone steals my sandwich, it's not immoral because he gets a free lunch; it's immoral because I don't get to eat.
But infringement is not like theft. It's more like trespass. If you trespass on my property, you have violated my rights. Even if there's no actual damages, I can collect nominal damages because you have wronged me.
Besides, if you hold this vew, then we're right back to the slavery counterexample. Owning a slave was a property right. Helping a slave escape infringed on that property right. If infringing on a property right was a priori unethical, then helping a slave escape his master would be unethical.
It's kind of a silly example since there is no slavery anymore in this country. As I said, slavery was wrong, even though it was legal. Not all property rights are good and moral. That's a great example of where we really got things wrong. I don't think that has anything to do with copyright. The property right itself was immoral in that situation. But you have to find an extreme example--where the property was a human being--to find an example where the property right was unjust. Copyright is just and right. Slavery was not.
If you hold a Lockean view of copyright (even vaguely), then it is not possible for Romero to "lose" that right. The film was the fruit of his labor, and the government doesn't have the right to deny him of that, any more than The Pirate Bay does.
I hold a Lockean view, even vaguely, and I think it's possible for him to lose that right. He knew going in that the right he was receiving was limited. There's nothing unfair about him losing the right. Once a work is in the public domain, no one owns it and everyone can use it. I'm not a strict Lockean, as I've said several times.
Since the "fruit of his labor" view is invalid, there must be some other reason that it's ethical for others to hold that "property right," while Romero doesn't. The only other reason you've given me is "the law says so," which is not an ethical reason.
He got a property right in the fruits of his labor. He knew that right was limited and was going to end. It ended. This seems eminently fair to me. There's more going on than his interests. There's the public interest as well, and I told you I like the utilitarian theory as well.
You brought up an irrelevant point only to distinguish it, and I'm pedantic? I don't see it.
OK, you want to argue "facts" in response to my "legal" assertion. Have at it. You haven't disproved that what I said is legally correct though, counselor.
I think it makes sense that more often than not the subscriber is the infringer. The other poster had mentioned the 70/30 number from one case. That "fact" supports the "legal" view.
I quoted the opinion of the court, not Mr. Randazza. There's other cases too that make the same point about how evidence of an IP address being used is prima facie evidence that the owner is an infringer. I think that's the correct view. All it means is that it's more likely than not.
Randazza is a character, I'll give you that. I thought his "leaving your wifi open is negligence" theory was stupid. I think he's a good attorney, though a bit too aggressive at times.
Digital rights management (DRM) is a class of access control technologies that are used by hardware manufacturers, publishers, copyright holders and individuals with the intent to limit the use of digital content and devices after sale.
Like I told bob last week, THAT is the definition of DRM. Which, as is rather obvious, DOES indeed violate a person's rights. Notably, "limit the use of digital content and devices after sale". Note that word "limit". Limit is "something that bounds, restrains, or confines". Do I go on?
Even if you have the right to copy something, it doesn't follow that it violates your rights to sell you something that is difficult to copy. Can you cite the source of your alleged right to be free from any limitation on your ability to copy?
That argument has been tried and failed:
Defendant relies heavily on congressional intent to preserve fair use but that congressional intent does not change the analysis. The Act expressly disclaims any intent to affect the rights, remedies, limitations, or defenses to copyright infringement, including the right of fair use. 17 U.S.C. § 1201(c). Congress' expressed intent to preserve the right of fair use is not inconsistent with a ban on trafficking in circumvention technologies, even those that could be used for fair use purposes rather than infringement. Fair use of a copyrighted work continues to be permitted, as does circumventing use restrictions for the purpose of engaging in a fair use, even though engaging in certain fair uses of digital works may be made more difficult if tools to circumvent use restrictions cannot be readily obtained.
The inescapable conclusion from the statutory language adopted by Congress and the legislative history discussed above is that Congress sought to ban all circumvention tools because most of the time those tools would be used to infringe a copyright. Thus, while it is not unlawful to circumvent for the purpose of engaging in fair use, it is unlawful to traffic in tools that allow fair use circumvention. That is part of the sacrifice Congress was willing to make in order to protect against unlawful piracy and promote the development of electronic commerce and the availability of copyrighted material on the Internet.
***
Defendant's arguments are not persuasive. First, the DMCA does not “eliminate” fair use. Although certain fair uses may become more difficult, no fair use has been prohibited. Lawful possessors of copyrighted works may continue to engage in each and every fair use authorized by law. It may, however, have become more difficult for such uses to occur with regard to technologically protected digital works, but the fair uses themselves have not been eliminated or prohibited.
For example, nothing in the DMCA prevents anyone from quoting from a work or comparing texts for the purpose of study or criticism. It may be that from a technological perspective, the fair user my find it more difficult to do so—quoting may have to occur the old fashioned way, by hand or by re-typing, rather than by “cutting and pasting” from existing digital media. Nevertheless, the fair use is still available. Defendant has cited no authority which guarantees a fair user the right to the most technologically convenient way to engage in fair use. The existing authorities have rejected that argument. See Corley, 273 F.3d at 459 (“We know of no authority for the proposition that fair use, as protected by the Copyright Act, much less the Constitution, guarantees copying by the optimum method or in the identical format of the original.... Fair use has never been held to be a guarantee of access to copyrighted material in order to copy it by the fair user's preferred technique or in the format of the original.”)
United States v. Elcom Ltd., 203 F. Supp. 2d 1111, 1125-31 (N.D. Cal. 2002).
Third, the Appellants have provided no support for their premise that fair use of DVD movies is constitutionally required to be made by copying the original work in its original format.34 Their examples of the fair uses that they believe others will be prevented from making all involve copying in a digital format those portions of a DVD movie amenable to fair use, a copying that would enable the fair user to manipulate the digitally copied portions. One example is that of a school child who wishes to copy images from a DVD movie to insert into the student's documentary film. We know of no authority for the proposition that fair use, as protected by the Copyright Act, much less the Constitution, guarantees copying by the optimum method or in the identical format of the original. Although the Appellants insisted at oral argument that they should not be relegated to a “horse and buggy” technique in making fair use of DVD movies,35 the DMCA does not impose even an arguable limitation on the opportunity to make a variety of traditional fair uses of DVD movies, such as commenting on their content, quoting excerpts from their screenplays, and even recording portions of the video images and sounds on film or tape by pointing a camera, a camcorder, or a microphone at a monitor as it displays the DVD movie. The fact that the resulting copy will not be as perfect or as manipulable as a digital copy obtained by having direct access to the DVD movie in its digital form, provides no basis for a claim of unconstitutional limitation of fair use. A film critic making fair use of a movie by quoting selected lines of dialogue has no constitutionally valid claim that the review (in print or on television) would be technologically superior if the reviewer had not been prevented from using a movie camera in the theater, nor has an art student a valid constitutional claim to fair use of a painting by photographing it in a museum. Fair use has never been held to be a guarantee of access to copyrighted material in order to copy it by the fair user's preferred technique or in the format of the original.
Universal City Studios, Inc. v. Corley, 273 F.3d 429, 459 (2d Cir. 2001).
I'm just not buying your arguments, and I'm not aware of any court that ever has.
70/30 was a ratio provided by the plaintiffs who admitted the error rate when asked about it. You don't think that this is problematic given the sheer number of settlement letters and threats they send out?
That was the admitted error rate in one case with one plaintiff. I have no idea what the number is in different cases, and neither do you. Even if that 30/70 is correct, that's still prima facie evidence (which just means more than 50% chance).
Captain Jean-Luc Picard, the man who defeated the Borg
If memory serves, the first time he encountered the Borg Q had to save his ass. The next time, Picard himself was assimilated as Locutus. Using the knowledge gained from Picard/Locutus, the Borg wipe out most of the fleet. It's Picard's crew that end up saving the day. I can't remember what happens in First Contact with the Borg Queen, but I think maybe Data saved the day there. Not sure though. Anyway, I don't remember Picard defeating the Borg.
That's just factually wrong. An IP address address does not even satisfy the "more likely than not" preponderance of the evidence burden in these civil cases, let alone the "beyond a reasonable doubt" standard that rightsholders and the government must meet in criminal copyright suits.
The "beyond a reasonable doubt" standard is irrelevant in these civil mass infringement cases. As far as the civil standard goes, can you cite one court that agrees with you?
I can find several that don't:
Thirteen putative defendants argue that they should be dismissed from the lawsuit because the plaintiff has improperly joined them with other putative defendants.17 The putative defendants' argument that they are improperly joined may be meritorious should they be named as defendants in this action. At this stage in the litigation, however, when discovery is *11 underway to learn identifying facts necessary to permit service on Doe defendants, joinder, under Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 20(a)(2), of unknown parties identified only by IP addresses is proper. As discussed below, this conclusion is further supported by the allegations set forth in the Complaint, which sufficiently establishes a prima facie case of infringement of plaintiff's copyrights by users of the same file-sharing software program that operates through simultaneous and sequential computer connections and data transfers among the users.
Maverick Entm't Group, Inc. v. Does 1-2,115, 810 F.Supp.2d 1, 10-11 (D.D.C. 2011).
In order to establish a claim for copyright infringement, Liberty Media must show that it holds a valid copyright and that the moving defendants violated one of their exclusive rights as the copyright owner. London–Sire Records, Inc. v. Doe 1, 542 F.Supp.2d 153, 165 (D.Mass.2008) (Gertner, J.); see 17 U.S.C. § 501. Liberty Media has produced sufficient evidence as to both these requirements to establish a prima facie claim. Liberty Media has shown that it holds a valid copyright to the Motion Picture, see Compl., Ex. 1, Certificate of Registration, ECF No. 1–1, and the copyright is not disputed here. Moreover, Liberty Media's investigator, Malte Dinkela, has demonstrated that Does 1–38 violated Liberty Media's exclusive right as the copyright owner to reproduce and distribute the copyrighted material.
Liberty Media Holdings, LLC v. Swarm Sharing Hash File, 821 F.Supp.2d 444, 449 (D. Mass. 2011).
If it is premature to sever based on possibility, why isn't is premature to file a frivolous lawsuit based on 70% possibility?
The lawsuit is what enables the plaintiff to gather information about the infringer. Without it, the plaintiff could not issue a subpoena to the ISP to get the subscribers' information. Plaintiffs could never go after anonymous infringers since they wouldn't even know where to begin. At that point, there isn't even a lawsuit against a named defendant. The lawsuit is against the Doe, whose identity the plaintiff doesn't even know yet. You seem to have a strange idea that lawsuits aren't filed until the plaintiff knows 100% that the defendant did it. That's not how it works. The lawsuit is what enables the plaintiff to gather more information via discovery.
70% likelihood of the alleged connection is not a prima facie case.
If a plaintiff has evidence that a subscriber's IP address was used to infringe on their copyrights, then the plaintiff has made out a prima facie case against that subscriber. The burden shifts to the defendant to make out some defense, and if the defendant can't or if they default, the plaintiff will win.
And I'm not convinced that the 70/30 thing is accurate for all cases.
Seriously? That is the point of attack you are taking?
Not an attack. I clicked on the "bags" link and found there isn't even one other article labeled as such. Just curious. Maybe Mike plans a series of post about bags.
Curious. Weren't you the person going on and on and on about how any violation of someone's "rights" was clearly "immoral."
You don't think spying on their personal communications outside of what the law qualifies as a violation of rights or being immoral?
And I said that if someone did something wrong, they should be punished. And the fact that they are tasked with upholding the law, it makes it all the more deplorable.
But you're skirting the question (surprising!): How does this story lead you to question whether they have "any legitimate evidence" about Dotcom's guilt? What does this have to do with all the evidence in the superseding indictment?
Once a Doe settles, there's no reason to press on with the lawsuit. So I don't understand your point. An IP address is enough to establish a prima facie case that the subscriber is the infringer, so I don't see the problem there either. Sure, the defendant might have some defense, but that doesn't negate the plaintiff's prima facie case.
I understand that some individual defendants probably have individual defenses that would make joinder impractical. But at this early stage of the proceedings, where no Doe defendant has even been named in the suit, I think it's premature to sever based on that possibility.
The deck is stacked because one victim is having his rights violated by thousands of infringers at a time. These lawsuits are a symptom of the problem, which is that it's not practical or possible for a victim to file a separate federal lawsuit for every separate infringer.
On the post: Funniest/Most Insightful Comments Of The Week At Techdirt
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
Obviously everyone's creations build upon the blocks that came before (Newton's comment about standing on the shoulders of giants comes to mind), but nonetheless copyrighted works are original to their author. As Feist makes clear, without originality, there is no copyright.
Second, whatever your take on these "property rights," they are certainly not Lockean.
My views are Lockean in that I think it's proper for an author to get a property right in the fruits of their intellectual labor, as I said. I also said I subscribe to other schools of thought as well. I'm not a staunch Lockean such that I think copyright is innate, must be perpetual, and there must not be fair use. I don't know what innate means, but I do think the idea of giving the author (and no one else) the property right is fair. Perhaps that's innate in some sense. I wouldn't mind if copyright were perpetual, but I accept that there's more going on than the author and I think the balance permitted by fair use and limited terms is also fair and serves countervailing interests.
In light of these two restrictions, it's really hard to see how Locke's theory of property should apply to copyright at all. Combine this with the unquestionable ethical wrongs that result in a Lockean "property view" of copyright, and I can say with confidence that holding this view is immoral.
I don't hold all of those views. I hold several views that overlap. As to how to apply Locke to copyright, I recommend Mossoff's paper: http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1983614
But it does show that if you're going to justify treating copyright as a "property right," it has to be for reasons that are not Locke's. You have to find some other way of showing how they are "fair."
I told you my view is simple. I think it's fair that authors should get a property right in their writings. That's exactly what it says in the Copyright Clause, so that makes me happy.
You do more than this. You say that copyright is entirely unlike other restrictions on speech. For example, you directly claimed that infringing speech is no more "speech" than prostitution. You claimed this specifically to justify protected speech being blocked. You have advocated this even before fair use or idea/expression determinations could be made. You have advocated this even when links to infringing speech result in the blocking of actual non-infringing speech.
I think we'd have to run through those arguments again. Sounds like you're referring to Arcara, where the Court rejected an argument that prostitution is imbued with enough protective speech/conduct to warrant heightened First Amendment scrutiny. I can't remember exactly what our disagreement was there, but I do remember thinking that you were making a circular argument.
Regardless, the case law and commentary has many references to how copyright is not a restriction on speech, as "copyright laws, of course, protect only the form of expression and not the ideas expressed." New York Times v. United States, 403 U.S. 713, 726, n.* (1971) (Brennan, J., concurring). The reason is because copyright doesn't lock up ideas, which is the evil that the First Amendment addresses.
Yet if you think anyone is even suggesting that protecting free speech justifies infringing on the "property right" of copyright holders, you claim they're "piracy apologists" who "just want stuff for free." You have never even considered that they might be defending free speech rights. You have never even considered that the right to free speech might justify allowing infringement, even temporarily. I'm betting that even reading these sentences makes you angry.
Not at all. I think I'd need a concrete example though, as it's hard for me to see it in the abstract.
You clearly think that copyright is vastly more important than free speech. This makes your opinion on whether "the inhibition is great" highly questionable, to say the least.
The First Amendment is more important, which is why copyright laws get First Amendment scrutiny. I have no problem with that, and I think the tests created by the Court are great.
And let's not forget that free speech rights are not the only rights that are in conflict with copyright. Holding a copyright means nothing other than that you have an ownership interest in the property of others. For the sake of argument, let's take the Lockean view of property. Copyright says that if I apply my own labor, using resources that I paid for, I do not own the fruits of that labor. At least, not if my fruits taste too much like yours.
I disagree with the premise that copyright means having an ownership interest in the property of others. And I don't really understand you. Copyright says you get a property right in the fruits of your labor, so long as you create something original (not novel, but original; I think you're mixing the two).
Being a monopoly, it's also a restraint on free trade. I don't know if you consider free trade any kind of "right," but at the very least, monopolies are not ethical.
If I write a book, I don't corner the entire book market. I have a monopoly over my book. That's not really a monopoly in the sense that I learned the word in macroeconomics. If my rights in my book are a monopoly, then all private property is a monopoly of sorts.
Theft is not immoral because it "infringes on a property right." It is immoral because it deprives the owner of the use of that property. If someone steals my sandwich, it's not immoral because he gets a free lunch; it's immoral because I don't get to eat.
But infringement is not like theft. It's more like trespass. If you trespass on my property, you have violated my rights. Even if there's no actual damages, I can collect nominal damages because you have wronged me.
Besides, if you hold this vew, then we're right back to the slavery counterexample. Owning a slave was a property right. Helping a slave escape infringed on that property right. If infringing on a property right was a priori unethical, then helping a slave escape his master would be unethical.
It's kind of a silly example since there is no slavery anymore in this country. As I said, slavery was wrong, even though it was legal. Not all property rights are good and moral. That's a great example of where we really got things wrong. I don't think that has anything to do with copyright. The property right itself was immoral in that situation. But you have to find an extreme example--where the property was a human being--to find an example where the property right was unjust. Copyright is just and right. Slavery was not.
If you hold a Lockean view of copyright (even vaguely), then it is not possible for Romero to "lose" that right. The film was the fruit of his labor, and the government doesn't have the right to deny him of that, any more than The Pirate Bay does.
I hold a Lockean view, even vaguely, and I think it's possible for him to lose that right. He knew going in that the right he was receiving was limited. There's nothing unfair about him losing the right. Once a work is in the public domain, no one owns it and everyone can use it. I'm not a strict Lockean, as I've said several times.
Since the "fruit of his labor" view is invalid, there must be some other reason that it's ethical for others to hold that "property right," while Romero doesn't. The only other reason you've given me is "the law says so," which is not an ethical reason.
He got a property right in the fruits of his labor. He knew that right was limited and was going to end. It ended. This seems eminently fair to me. There's more going on than his interests. There's the public interest as well, and I told you I like the utilitarian theory as well.
On the post: When Captain Picard Loses Patience With Your Cable Service, You Need To Run A Tighter Ship
Re: Re:
On the post: When Captain Picard Loses Patience With Your Cable Service, You Need To Run A Tighter Ship
Re: Re:
On the post: Another Judge Blasts Copyright Trolls
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
OK, you want to argue "facts" in response to my "legal" assertion. Have at it. You haven't disproved that what I said is legally correct though, counselor.
I think it makes sense that more often than not the subscriber is the infringer. The other poster had mentioned the 70/30 number from one case. That "fact" supports the "legal" view.
What are your "facts"? Let's take a look.
On the post: Another Judge Blasts Copyright Trolls
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
Randazza is a character, I'll give you that. I thought his "leaving your wifi open is negligence" theory was stupid. I think he's a good attorney, though a bit too aggressive at times.
On the post: Another Judge Blasts Copyright Trolls
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
Like I told bob last week, THAT is the definition of DRM. Which, as is rather obvious, DOES indeed violate a person's rights. Notably, "limit the use of digital content and devices after sale". Note that word "limit". Limit is "something that bounds, restrains, or confines". Do I go on?
Even if you have the right to copy something, it doesn't follow that it violates your rights to sell you something that is difficult to copy. Can you cite the source of your alleged right to be free from any limitation on your ability to copy?
That argument has been tried and failed: United States v. Elcom Ltd., 203 F. Supp. 2d 1111, 1125-31 (N.D. Cal. 2002). Universal City Studios, Inc. v. Corley, 273 F.3d 429, 459 (2d Cir. 2001).
I'm just not buying your arguments, and I'm not aware of any court that ever has.
On the post: Another Judge Blasts Copyright Trolls
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
That was the admitted error rate in one case with one plaintiff. I have no idea what the number is in different cases, and neither do you. Even if that 30/70 is correct, that's still prima facie evidence (which just means more than 50% chance).
On the post: When Captain Picard Loses Patience With Your Cable Service, You Need To Run A Tighter Ship
If memory serves, the first time he encountered the Borg Q had to save his ass. The next time, Picard himself was assimilated as Locutus. Using the knowledge gained from Picard/Locutus, the Borg wipe out most of the fleet. It's Picard's crew that end up saving the day. I can't remember what happens in First Contact with the Borg Queen, but I think maybe Data saved the day there. Not sure though. Anyway, I don't remember Picard defeating the Borg.
On the post: Another Judge Blasts Copyright Trolls
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
The "beyond a reasonable doubt" standard is irrelevant in these civil mass infringement cases. As far as the civil standard goes, can you cite one court that agrees with you?
I can find several that don't: Maverick Entm't Group, Inc. v. Does 1-2,115, 810 F.Supp.2d 1, 10-11 (D.D.C. 2011).
On the post: Another Judge Blasts Copyright Trolls
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
I didn't say it was, nor would I. Nor do I understand how anyone's due process rights are being violated. Can you explain?
On the post: Another Judge Blasts Copyright Trolls
Re: Re: Re: Re:
It's all around you. See, e.g., Liberty Media Holdings, LLC v. Swarm Sharing Hash File, 821 F.Supp.2d 444, 449 (D. Mass. 2011).
On the post: Another Judge Blasts Copyright Trolls
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
What specifically makes it illegal for you to format shift?
What about my right to make a backup copy that is voided because of a crappy piece of DRM code?
DRM doesn't violate your rights.
Why is it the rights of corporations are more important to you than regular people?
Everybody's rights are important.
On the post: Another Judge Blasts Copyright Trolls
Re:
On the post: Another Judge Blasts Copyright Trolls
Re: Re: Re: Re:
The lawsuit is what enables the plaintiff to gather information about the infringer. Without it, the plaintiff could not issue a subpoena to the ISP to get the subscribers' information. Plaintiffs could never go after anonymous infringers since they wouldn't even know where to begin. At that point, there isn't even a lawsuit against a named defendant. The lawsuit is against the Doe, whose identity the plaintiff doesn't even know yet. You seem to have a strange idea that lawsuits aren't filed until the plaintiff knows 100% that the defendant did it. That's not how it works. The lawsuit is what enables the plaintiff to gather more information via discovery.
70% likelihood of the alleged connection is not a prima facie case.
If a plaintiff has evidence that a subscriber's IP address was used to infringe on their copyrights, then the plaintiff has made out a prima facie case against that subscriber. The burden shifts to the defendant to make out some defense, and if the defendant can't or if they default, the plaintiff will win.
And I'm not convinced that the 70/30 thing is accurate for all cases.
On the post: Unfortunate: Kickstarter's Overaggressive Reaction To DMCA Notices
Re: Re:
Not an attack. I clicked on the "bags" link and found there isn't even one other article labeled as such. Just curious. Maybe Mike plans a series of post about bags.
On the post: Unfortunate: Kickstarter's Overaggressive Reaction To DMCA Notices
On the post: NZ Prime Minister Admits That The Government Illegally Wiretapped Megaupload Employees
Re: Re:
You don't think spying on their personal communications outside of what the law qualifies as a violation of rights or being immoral?
And I said that if someone did something wrong, they should be punished. And the fact that they are tasked with upholding the law, it makes it all the more deplorable.
But you're skirting the question (surprising!): How does this story lead you to question whether they have "any legitimate evidence" about Dotcom's guilt? What does this have to do with all the evidence in the superseding indictment?
On the post: Another Judge Blasts Copyright Trolls
Re: Re:
I understand that some individual defendants probably have individual defenses that would make joinder impractical. But at this early stage of the proceedings, where no Doe defendant has even been named in the suit, I think it's premature to sever based on that possibility.
On the post: Another Judge Blasts Copyright Trolls
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
On the post: Another Judge Blasts Copyright Trolls
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
Next >>