RIAA Lawyers Trying To Rewrite History Of Copyright Clause Through Shoddy Scholarship And Selective Quotation
from the must-pay-well dept
Over the last week or so, I've seen a number of folks in the usual crowd of copyright maximalists cheering on a new "paper" put forth by a group hilariously calling itself the Center for Individual Freedom, supposedly trying to establish the "constitutional and historical foundations of copyright protection." The "paper" (and I use that term loosely) itself does no such thing. It's a one-sided polemic about why copyright is property -- argued by selectively quoting a few historical claims, often out of context, and ignoring everything else. The six page document (quick read) was actually written by three lawyers... who admit that they work for the RIAA. The basic argument is that copyright is a "natural right," and that this idea was well established at the time of the Constitution. The framing, then, is that all the Constitution was really doing was codifying a natural right that all agreed was akin to property, and that this right cannot and should not be diminished or taken away.To do this, the authors rely, almost exclusively, on some arguments that John Locke made. This is the go to move of copyright maximalists. Because John Locke argued that property rights were established as a result of one's labor, and thus a "natural right", and some of the founders were influenced by John Locke, voila, copyright was meant to be given as a natural right. As the paper notes:
The foundational premise of Locke's theory is that all people have a natural right of property in their own bodies. Because people own their bodies, Locke reasoned that they also owned the labor of their bodies and, by extension, the fruits of that labor. When an individual catches a fish in a stream, he has a right to keep that fish because but-for his efforts, the fish would not have been caught. For the same reason, an author has a right to his works because his efforts made the work possible. Under Locke’s view, "[o]ur handiwork becomes our property because our hands—and the energy, consciousness, and control that fuel their labor--are our property."Nearly all of this is misleading or out of context. Or just wrong. The idea that Locke was arguing that mere labor alone creates a property right is just silly. As Stephan Kinsella pointed out years ago, this argument makes little sense the more you think about it, as Kinsella demonstrates by talking about who owns a loaf of bread:
That is, "a person rightly claims ownership in her works to the extent that her labor resulted in their existence." If anything, under Locke's theory, intellectual property should be even more worthy of protection than physical property. Land and natural resources are pre-existing and finite, and one person's acquisition of a piece of tangible property may reduce the "common" that is available to others. Not so with tangible expressions: the field of creative works is infinite, and one person's expression of an idea does not meaningfully deplete the opportunities available to others; indeed, it expands the size of the "pie" by providing inspiration to others. Moreover, while tangible property such as land and chattel is often pre-existing and acquired through mere happenstance of birth, intellectual property flows directly from its creator and is essentially the "propertization of talent"--that is, "a reward, an empowering instrument, for the talented upstarts" in a society.
But creation of the loaf is not the reason why the baker owns it. He owns the loaf because he owned the dough that he baked. He already owned the dough, before any act of "creation"--before he transformed it with his labor. If he owned the dough, then he owns whatever he transforms his property into; the act of creation is an act of transformation that does not generate any new property rights. So creation is not necessary for him to own the resulting baked bread. Likewise, if he used someone else's dough--say, his employer's--then he does not own the loaf, but the owner of the dough does. So creation is not sufficient for ownership.Creation is not sufficient for ownership. That should be obvious, but for some reason the paper assumes that it must be so.
Oh, and Locke actually had much more mixed feelings on copyright. As some have pointed out, back in Locke's time, there was the precursor to copyright, known as The Stationers' Company monopoly, which more or less later morphed into the Statute of Anne (the basis for much of modern copyright). Locke's opinion on the Stationer's Company Monopoly? Not good at all. He argued vehemently against it, and is widely credited by some for it not being renewed. While he did support some of the ideas that were discussed for the eventual Statute of Anne, many of his ideas were actually rejected when that bill came around. As has been noted elsewhere, the Parliament explicitly rejected an earlier version of the Statute of Anne that referred to it as a property right (which also made it unlimited), completely changing the text to note that it was for the promotion of learning.
The central plank of the 1710 Act was then, and remains, a cultural quid pro quo. Parliament, to encourage "learned Men to compose and write useful Books", provided a guaranteed, if finite, right to print and reprint those works so composed. The legislators were not concerned with the recognition of any pre-existing authorial right, nor were they solely interested in the regulation of the bookseller's market.And yet, the RIAA laywers make a big stink about Locke's impact on the Statute of Anne. They ignore that many of his ideas were rejected by Parliament, and instead pretend that he more or less wrote the damn thing.
In the 1690s, Parliament refused to renew the Stationers’ Company’s printing monopoly, and authors and booksellers in the newly competitive industry began pressing for formal protection for their works. Although he strongly opposed the Stationers’ Company’s monopoly, John Locke himself described literary publications as “property” and argued in a 1694 letter to Parliament that formal publishing rights should last for the life of the author plus seventy years.Yes, because during the debate over what to do about this, Locke referred to publishing rights (not copyright, by the way) as property, these lawyers claim it was a key basis for copyright. Except... they leave out the part where Parliament rejected most of Locke's suggestions and went in a different direction. It's the details like this that matter.
In 1710, Parliament enacted the Statute of Anne, which formally granted authors of existing works a 21-year exclusive publication right and authors of new works a renewable 14-year exclusive right.
Furthermore, much of the argument in the paper is that Locke believe copyright is some sort of "natural right," rather than a utilitarian issue (i.e., for the betterment of society). And yet, when you look at all of Locke's comments on the matter, even when he's making what appears to be a natural rights argument, it's really a utilitarian argument in disguise. The RIAA lawyers accidentally make that very point when they argue that Locke would have supported copyright more than traditional property (while ignoring the fact that he quite obviously did not) because it would "increase the pie." But, of course, increasing the pie is a utilitarian argument. Which is exactly what Locke was making when it came to such works, contrary to the claims of the authors of the paper.
The paper then makes the further leap that since the US's Copyright Clause had similarities to the Statute of Anne, that the founders also believed wholeheartedly in the (already not really accurate) idea that he thought copyright was property. Derek Bambauer, in talking about just how inaccurate and ridiculous the RIAA paper is, reminds us of Dotan Oliar's incredibly detailed paper on the origins of the US Copyright Clause, which should be required reading for anyone arguing about this clause and what it actually means. As that paper shows in much more detail than anything the RIAA lawyers wrote, the RIAA's claims are, well, bunk. Oliar looks at the historical record of the various proposals put forth for the copyright clause, and notes that Congress explicitly rejected the ones that were more based on a "natural rights" or "property rights" view, and like the English Parliament before them, chose instead to support a limited bill for the purpose of promoting progress, rather than any sort of property right.
Specifically, the study of the Convention’s record provides three indications that the Framers intended the Progress Clause as a limitation on Congress’s intellectual property power. First, Madison and Pinckney’s initial proposals to vest patent and copyright powers in Congress were plenary and did not include language relating to the promotion of progress in science and useful arts. Had the Framers been content with such plenary patent and copyright powers, they would have likely adopted them as proposed. The Framers’ choice not to adopt the plenary proposals, but rather to subject their exercise to specific ends, tends to prove that the Progress Clause was added as a limitation.That paper, unlike the RIAA paper, is quite detailed and thorough (and actually acknowledges the views of those who have argued otherwise, before explaining why the evidence suggests they're wrong). Reading through the details there, you're left with a pretty convincing case that the majority of framers of the Constitution were not looking to secure some sort of "natural right" or "property right," but to explicitly to use the "promote the progress" clause to limit Congress' ability to do damage with copyrights and patents. Yes, there were some who viewed copyright as a natural rights issue, but it is clearly not the majority, or else they wouldn't have rejected putting such language forward. Besides, the fact that in a large group of politicians, you can find a few to make a crazy argument does not mean that the entire body agreed with those views. Can you imagine what these lawyers must think of Congress? One Rep suggests raising taxes and they must think that, clearly, the entire country supports raising taxes. Because that seems to be the only way their argument in this paper makes any sense.
The RIAA paper also brings up the UN's declaration on human rights, arguing that its Article 27 shows that it is a widespread belief that copyright is a natural property right. Except, as we've discussed in great detail, this is not what the declaration on human rights actually says. Not only does that same clause argue that "everyone has the right to freely participate in the cultural life of the community, to enjoy the arts," but official commentary and associated declarations also, explicitly, note that the rights being discussed do not equate to copyright and should not be equated with copyright. Not surprisingly, the RIAA paper ignores all of that.
It also ignores some key US cases, which flatly reject this idea, including the 1834 decision in Wheaton v. Peters -- considered the first real copyright case in the Supreme Court, in which the Supreme Court comes down pretty firmly against the idea of copyright as a natural right, and establishes that it is a creature purely of statute. In fact, the court there refers back to the Statute of Anne as well, and notes that there, too, they have rejected the natural rights argument for copyright.
No such right at the common law had been recognized in England, when the colony of Penn was organized. Long afterwards, literary property became a subject of controversy, but the question was involved in great doubt and perplexity; and a little more than a century ago, it was decided by the highest judicial court in England, that the right of authors could not be asserted at common law, but under the statute. The statute of Anne was passed in 1710.The court then went much further in noting that the Constitution explicitly presents limits on copyright, and there is no evidence that it was establishing the recognition of a natural right:
That congress, in passing the act of 1790, did not legislate in reference to existing rights, appears clear, from the provision that the author, &c. "shall have the sole right and liberty of printing," &c. Now if this exclusive right existed at common law, and congress were about to adopt legislative provisions for its protection, would they have used this language? Could they have deemed it necessary to vest a right already vested. Such a presumption is refuted by the words above quoted, and their force is not lessened by any other part of the act.This case is widely known to copyright scholars. It seems rather stunning that these RIAA lawyers (or the CFIF, which published the paper) would be ignorant of it. Thus, it's not difficult to conclude from all of this that the authors of the paper did not undertake a scholarly look at whether or not copyright was long viewed as a natural right and thus, as property, but rather that they cherry picked a few quotes out of context, and then pretended those quotes had much more impact than they really did.
Congress, then, by this act, instead of sanctioning an existing right, as contended for, created it. This seems to be the clear import of the law, connected with the circumstances under which it was enacted.
Thank you for reading this Techdirt post. With so many things competing for everyone’s attention these days, we really appreciate you giving us your time. We work hard every day to put quality content out there for our community.
Techdirt is one of the few remaining truly independent media outlets. We do not have a giant corporation behind us, and we rely heavily on our community to support us, in an age when advertisers are increasingly uninterested in sponsoring small, independent sites — especially a site like ours that is unwilling to pull punches in its reporting and analysis.
While other websites have resorted to paywalls, registration requirements, and increasingly annoying/intrusive advertising, we have always kept Techdirt open and available to anyone. But in order to continue doing so, we need your support. We offer a variety of ways for our readers to support us, from direct donations to special subscriptions and cool merchandise — and every little bit helps. Thank you.
–The Techdirt Team
Filed Under: copyright clause, history, john locke, natural rights, statute of anne, utilitarian
Companies: riaa
Reader Comments
The First Word
“Subscribe: RSS
View by: Time | Thread
I'll be reading Oliar's paper for sure.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re:
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
So the part you're missing is that the House of Lords acknowledged that there was in fact a natural right to copyright. That natural right was superseded by statute, but that's not the point. The point is that but for the Statute of Anne, the House of Lords recognized that authors had natural rights to the fruits of their intellectual labor.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re:
" But creation of the loaf is not the reason why the baker owns it. He owns the loaf because he owned the dough that he baked. He already owned the dough, before any act of "creation"--before he transformed it with his labor. If he owned the dough, then he owns whatever he transforms his property into; the act of creation is an act of transformation that does not generate any new property rights. So creation is not necessary for him to own the resulting baked bread. Likewise, if he used someone else's dough--say, his employer's--then he does not own the loaf, but the owner of the dough does. So creation is not sufficient for ownership."
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re:
Perhaps I don't understand what a natural right is, but I thought it was a right that needed no government to give it.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re:
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re:
However you misread the British Constitution of the time - according to which the whole House of Lords - not just the Law Lords made the decision.
The detaails are here http://copy.law.cam.ac.uk/cam/tools/request/showRecord.php?id=record_uk_1774
"the House of Lords, in line with the majority of the law lords who spoke to the issue, rejected the argument in favour of common law copyright, but that the significance of this decision was nevertheless obscured as a result of the manner in which the opinions of the judges and the law lords was subsequently recorded and reported."
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Bootstraps!
The reason for this particular confusion lies in the fact that the Lord Chancellor's first question, as to whether an author had the "right of first printing and publishing" his work at common law, can be read in two different ways. The first presupposes the existence of copyright, as an intangible property right, at common law - that is, a right to publish and re-publish one's work to the exclusion of all others. The second, however, relates to the existence of a right at common law which flows from the ownership of the physical object, the manuscript - in this case, a right of first publication (in essence, a right to divulge) and nothing more.
That is - in order to show that the Lords believed copyright already existed you need to assume that people generally accepted that copyright already existed - in other words the copyright argument is pulling itself up by its own bootstraps.
The right to first divulge, on the other hand is generally accepted- even Crosbie Fitch accepts that!
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Bootstraps!
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Bootstraps!
And I blogged a response to Bambauer (he hasn't 'yet' published my comment on his article):
Derek Bambauer suggests the cartel’s attempt to frame copyright as ‘a natural right to be secured’ is greenwashing. I suggest it is because they’ve recognised I have a point – the US Constitution did not empower the granting of a privilege. See my argument with Karl
The US Constitution empowers Congress to SECURE the author’s (“solemnly adjudged to be a common law”) right to exclude others from their writings for limited times.
In 1787, in the New World and Old, most of those in the publishing industry were kidding themselves that a reproduction monopoly was a natural right and that the Statute of Anne (and various states’ legislative imitations) was a paltry legal recognition thereof. This is why James Madison (despite Jefferson’s suggestion to explicitly empower the granting of monopolies) knew he only needed to empower Congress to secure a right, in order to grant the monopoly of copyright.
By legislating the first US copyright act (Statute of Anne with minor edits) in 1790, most of those interested would accept this as the securing of a natural right (despite the fact that Madison & Jefferson knew damn well that copyright was the granting of a monopoly, not the securing of a right) – “That to secure these rights, Governments are instituted among Men, deriving their just powers from the consent of the governed”.
Madison (who wanted copyright enacted) knew that a clause empowering Congress to grant monopolies would not have been ratified, hence his insertion of a clause that ‘secured a right’ – a pre-existing right (“endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights”).
The point is, although the clause was APPARENTLY sufficient to enable Madison/Congress to grant copyright (by way of securing a common law right as others would assume) it was not ACTUALLY sufficient. Copyright is the grant of a monopoly and not at all law that secures a common law right.
So, Congress did not have power to grant copyright. It only had power to secure an author’s natural right to exclude others from their writings, i.e. our physical power to exclude burglars from copying our writings, such as our memoirs in our desk drawers (a natural right) – not to exclude those who purchase copies of those memoirs from us, from making and distributing their own copies (a privilege).
So, the cartel, conceding that the US Constitution empowered only the securing of a natural right, must now pretend that a reproduction monopoly is a natural right. And like James Madison, they will lead their audience to believe this without actually asserting it.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re:
The detaails are here http://copy.law.cam.ac.uk/cam/tools/request/showRecord.php?id=record_uk_1774
"the House of Lords, in line with the majority of the law lords who spoke to the issue, rejected the argument in favour of common law copyright, but that the significance of this decision was nevertheless obscured as a result of the manner in which the opinions of the judges and the law lords was subsequently recorded and reported."
I'm not misreading the British Constitution. Perhaps the Supreme Court was. I'm just quoting what was said in Wheaton. There it says that a majority of the Lords held that there was in fact common law copyright but that it was then later superseded by statute. I understand that you're saying that it was the Law Lords and not the whole House of Lords and that perhaps the House of Lords said something different. I'll have to read through the materials there to see. I'm not very well versed in appellate procedures of 18th century England, and perhaps neither was the Supreme Court. That might explain the error if there was one.
Nonetheless, the fact remains that courts of equity were enjoining copying before there was statutory copyright. In my mind, that's the definition of common law copyright. The fact also remains that in the U.S. there was also common law copyright in the states--as there still is to this day.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
As others already said which you choose to ignore as usual
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re:
Except that this statement is itself incorrect.
The majority of the Law Lords voted this way - but the House of Lords voted the other way.
This was generally acknowledged at the time - even by the stationers company themselves. Just 6 days later they wrote
"[B]y a late solemn decision of the House of Peerssuch common law right of authors and their assigns hath been declared to have no existence, whereby your petitioners will be very great sufferers thro' their involuntary misapprehension of the law".
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re:
Except that this statement is itself incorrect.
The majority of the Law Lords voted this way - but the House of Lords voted the other way.
This was generally acknowledged at the time - even by the stationers company themselves. Just 6 days later they wrote
"[B]y a late solemn decision of the House of Peerssuch common law right of authors and their assigns hath been declared to have no existence, whereby your petitioners will be very great sufferers thro' their involuntary misapprehension of the law".
I read that quote as meaning that there was no common law copyright because it has been superseded by the Statute of Anne, which is what the Lords said in Donaldson (as reported by the Supreme Court in Wheaton). That's not contradictory.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re:
"Lord Chancellor Apsley, like Lord Camden, explicitly denied the existence of any common law right, ab initio, and it was this position that the majority of the peers embraced."
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re:
Richard is already debunking this claim, but even if your basic claim was accurate, it actually works against your argument. At best it shows that SOME people believed they were natural rights (and we all agree that some did), but that they were OVERRULED in the end by people saying there was no natural rights there.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re:
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re:
You're still missing the point. The majority in Donaldson said there was common law copyright that was thereafter preempted by the Statute of Anne. You're trying to say that there was no common law copyright, i.e., that it's not natural. But that's not what they said in Donaldson.
The point is that there are natural rights in copyright that developed in the common law, but then later the statutes codified and preempted those rights. You are twisting this to mean that there is no natural right in copyright. That's not at all the case. There is a natural right. That right was protected at common law at first, and then later it was protected by statute.
In fact, the Supreme Court later on recognized that there is in fact common law copyright that is superseded by statute (contrary to what was said in Wheaton): Holmes v. Hurst, 174 U.S. 82, 84-85 (1899).
So there the Supreme Court says that there was common law copyright. The fact remains that the common law recognized copyright rights, and then later the statutory laws preempted much of those rights. That doesn't at all negate the fact that copyright is natural.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re:
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Re:
The court in Wheaton was talking about "common law" as a synonym of "natural law." Later courts, however, seem to equate "common law" with "case law."
In any case, copyright is neither. The fact that Holmes v. Hurst talks about the Star Chamber and the Stationers' Monopoly should make this clear. Neither of these were "copyright" in the modern sense of the term - neither claimed (nor even suggested) that authors had either a natural or common-law right to a post-publication monopoly.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
It's funny you say that because I got that Holmes case from Patry's treatise: 1 Patry on Copyright § 1:19.
So the Supreme Court in Holmes took back what it said earlier in Wheaton about the nonexistence of common law copyright. It's not clear to me whether that's referring to state or federal common law, but nonetheless the Court did change their story on the point.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re:
However, even if you believe that to be correct, the vast majority of our collected culture is derived from other pieces of culture. Take, for example, archaeology. If things haven't been catalogued by location, etcetera, then the cultural perceptions we have as a result are useless.
The major thing about Perceptional Properties, such as copyright, is that if it didn't exist, there would be no physical harm that could be proven. With Perceptional Property laws, there is provable harm as they stand today.
Props, at least, for having citations to back up your assertions.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Re:
Please provide some examples/citations of "provable" "physical" harm.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
Maybe it wasn't as clear as I thought when i wrote the above.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re:
Read my comment - read the site that I referenced - and you will see that your statement above is flat out wrong!
How many times do I have to tell you??
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Re:
I'm quoting what the Supreme Court said in Wheaton. I quoted the exact text and it says what I'm saying it says. I understand that some professor wrote something a couple of years ago that you think says something else. I will read it, as I said.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
In Ronan Deazley's earlier, 2003 article “The myth of copyright at common law” (Cambridge Law Journal), he wrote, regarding Wheaton v Peters:
But it is not clear to me in (re-)reading Mr Justice McLean's 1834 opinion that he then thought that courts of the United States of America ought to be in any way bound by a 1774 decision of the English House of Lords. Rather, it seems more clear to me that he consulted the English authorities for their pursuasive value.
That is to say, it is not clear to me that Mr Justice McLean was in any way at all concerned with the collective opinion of the House, or in their decision that “[t]he decree of the Court of Chancery was accordingly reversed”.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re:
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re:
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
I read it, and understood it, but it failed to enlighten me.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re:
It cannot provide such a basis because the assertions themselves are incorrect.
For an objective view of the subject this site is a priceless resource.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re:
Prior to the start of printing, only attribution of authors existed, as the copying of books was labour intensive, literally writing out a copy. Only the ultra rich, and the church could afford any books. The church was the major producer of books, and scientists, as it had the monks to carry out the copying of books.
Also note that University education was based on a religious education, and students had to copy any manuscripts they wished to keep a copy of.
The printing press upset the established order by making it possible to produce books at a more reasonable cost. Control over printing was attempted by both church and state because it threatened the established order. (does this sound familiar with respect to the internet and the more repressive regimes). Some countries established licences to produce copies, as a form of controlling the information that was made available. In England this was centred in the stationers company, who controlled what was printed on behalf of the crown. In effect the stationers controlled what work was printed as censors over authors.
When this censorship monopoly was removed, the stationers cam up with the idea of copyright so that they could continue to control printing. This right had little to do with paying authors, who were paid under the previous system, but was intended to allow the stationers to keep control over printing. That is all the fuss about the rights of authors was political spin, so that the stationer could regain some of their former monopoly, copyright limited the length of the monopoly, where the previous censorship regime did not limit the length of the monopoly, it was presumed to last forever.
Performance of music stayed outside of the copyright system until the player pianos threatened the income of sheet music publishers.
When recording came along John Philip Sousa said :-
This implies that public performance was not under copyright control.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re:
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Where do natural rights come from?
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Where do natural rights come from?
And all of this protest is for naught anyway. Copyright has been around for hundreds of years and will be around for hundreds more.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Where do natural rights come from?
only a tiny tiny fraction of the time compared to how long there was no copyright
people thought the same about the prohibition, and we all know how that worked out
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Okay, let's twist that around a little. Let's say I have a published book in front of me, and I also have pen and paper or a computer with a word processor program open. I then take the time and effort to rewrite/retype the book, word for word. I have done labour. I have exerted effort. Do I not own the resultant book? And what about if I employ a short-cut? Instead of manually re-typing every word, I just use Ctrl+C and Ctrl+V?
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re:
These lawyers and everyone else needs to get it through their heads. Copyright is not property. It's not even a right. It's a limitation of everyone else's rights to make copies. Copyright doesn't grant you anything, it takes something away from everyone else.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
@ "But creation of the loaf is not the reason why the baker owns it."
There was labor that went into farming, harvesting, and processing the flour. LABOR IS THE BASIS OF ALL WEALTH. You can dream up all the Twinkies (or IPADS) you want, but until those in the physical chain actually produce the goods, you've got bupkis.
Now, non-physical goods (the content) is produced by a more complex chain -- that I'm certainly not even going to attempt to outline to someone who thinks bread flour pops out of the air -- but it's still REAL ENOUGH to determine who OWNS it by the act of creating it.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: @ "But creation of the loaf is not the reason why the baker owns it."
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: @ "But creation of the loaf is not the reason why the baker owns it."
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: @ "But creation of the loaf is not the reason why the baker owns it."
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: @ "But creation of the loaf is not the reason why the baker owns it."
Okay, let's talk about the farmer. The milling of the grains is not why he owns the flour. The harvesting of the wheat is not why he owns the grains. The tending of the land is not why he owns the wheat.
At no point is a new property right formed by the act of transformation. It's always building on standard, existing property rights -- the land he bought, the seeds he bought -- just as it is with the baker and the flour he bought.
If the farmer hires someone to tend his wheat and turn it into flour, he doesn't forfeit ownership of it. If someone raids his crops and turns the wheat into flour themselves, they don't gain ownership by act of creation. Creation has nothing to do with it. Physical creation is just the rearrangement of existing physical property rights into forms that make them more valuable (or at least that's usually the goal).
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: @ "But creation of the loaf is not the reason why the baker owns it."
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: @ "But creation of the loaf is not the reason why the baker owns it."
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: @
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: @ "But creation of the loaf is not the reason why the baker owns it."
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: @ "But creation of the loaf is not the reason why the baker owns it."
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Another point I think you're missing is that the Supreme Court in Wheaton said there was no FEDERAL common law copyright. That's not that surprising since there was federal statutory copyright right from the start which would have preempted any such claim anyway. The Court did not say that there was no state common law copyright--which there in fact was and in fact still is in some states.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re:
The 2008 Pro-Ip act helped eliminate sovereign immunity for almost all states.
So now, federal law trumps state law in this regard.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re:
The only rights preempted under 301(a) are those equivalent to the rights under 106 concerning works within federal copyright subject matter. You're right that many rights were preempted by the 1976 Act, but you're missing that some state-granted rights were not. I know that my state has copyright rights that were not preempted, and I believe that many if not all other states do as well.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re:
Quite literally, it's harming the industry as the Library of Congress works to update their files on those copyrights and tries to enforce both state and federal copyright.
One example would be jazz music suffering under copyright. You might be able to use a melody, but older musicians long gone are bound by state laws that are very much outdated.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re:
Uh, no, they did say this, explicitly:
In other words, if there are State copyrights, they are not common-law copyrights either, but determined entirely by state statutes. State copyright laws are equally as much "a creature of statute" as Federal copyright law.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re:
Nope. Here's the New York Court of Appeals (the state's highest court) 1n 1872 saying there are non-statutory common law copyrights in : Palmer v. De Witt, 47 N.Y. 532, 535-36 (1872).
Note too how the court comfortably calls it "property."
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re:
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Re:
I'm not trying to rewrite anything. I'm trying to understand the past because it's important that we get it right when using the past to make policy arguments today, which is what we're doing. Mike is of the opinion that copyright is purely an economic regulation, completely devoid of any natural rights origin. I think that's bunk, and there's a rich history of natural rights theory and treatment of copyright as property. If anything, I think Mike is the one trying to rewrite history as he ignores all of the evidence that the Framers held Lockean notions of copyright. My understanding is that they held multiple views, utilitarian and natural, and that copyright is a product of a plurality of views. Mike seems to think that the very Framers whom he admits held Lockean views nonetheless completely eschewed those views when granting authors a statutory right to the fruits of their intellectual labor. I don't think that makes any sense.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
After the printing press, copyright was a license granted by a censor to allow printing and distribution of a work.
See Imprimatur
and Stationers Company
Which are the origins of copyright, and had nothing to do with authors rights, but rather control over what was published.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Natural_law
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
Copyrights are a barrier to those simple natural facts.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
That's what modern copyright is all about, too. You have selective vision.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
Yeah, right. You did not try (and fail) to rewrite the definition of property the other day? Good, that you at least admitted to lying.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
LEAVE AJ ALONE! LEAVE HER ALONE! :)
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re:
Yep. Palmer v. De Witt was talking about the "first publication" right - that is, a property right in unpublished manuscripts. Of course those are private property, because they have not yet been divulged to the rest of mankind through publication; they are still the author's private possession.
Even Wheaton v. Peters acknowledges that this is a common-law right - immediately before they say that a post-publication monopoly is not:
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Re:
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
As Post says: "As a historical matter, I think they’re dead wrong."..."I also think they’re wrong, on the merits"
Post also observes that this paper appears to be a response to the recent Derek Khanna policy brief published and then withdrawn by the Republican Study Committee. The implication is that Clement is trying to influence originalist members of the GOP into thinking the founders believed in some natural right to intellectual property.
It is therefore well to consider that Thomas Jefferson directly addressed the question of natural rights with respect to what we now call 'intellectual property'. Thomas Jefferson, Letter to Isaac McPherson, Monticello, August 13, 1813
...And yes, I know Jefferson was specifically talking about patents, but the issues he discussed in the letter apply to copyright as well.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Of course they ignore the actual wording of the article.
"(1) Everyone has the right freely to participate in the cultural life of the community, to enjoy the arts and to share in scientific advancement and its benefits.
(2) Everyone has the right to the protection of the moral and material interests resulting from any scientific, literary or artistic production of which he is the author."
The first part seems to preclude using copyright to limit the spread of culture and speech, so DMCA takedowns being used to censor speech would be violations of human rights.
The second part specifically states, "of which he is the author," which doesn't seem to be support the concept of transferability of IP. Corporations, not being people, cannot be authors of works. Non-humans cannot hold human rights. So even if copyright were a human right, it wouldn't be applicable to non-human entities, contrary to what Mitt Romney and friends think.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
But that is what lawyers do, cheery pick whatever makes their clients look good--then bury the rest.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re:
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
This sounds more like the classical argument against slavery rather than copyright--that a person cannot be deprived the right over their own personhood, and by extension, their labor--and thus an argument against the RIAA's enforcement of publishers ownership of their artist.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Who cares about natural rights? The statute is good enough
All of the endless debates around here are either about (1) obscure edge conditions or (2) obviously guilty people grasping at straws. But the obscure edge conditions rarely happen. For the most part, if you see someone's intellectual property and you make a copy for others like the file sharing people do, it's clearly infringement. The courts have almost always treated it as such and they will continue to do so.
It's almost always cut and dried even though all of the piracy apologists would like to believe that the courts are somehow going to buy into the looney ramblings and dreams. To whit, look at the success of Napster, MP3.com, Jammie Thomas, Legg Mason and pretty much anyone else who tried to blather on and on about "artificial scarcity" or other interesting but irrelevant theories.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Who cares about natural rights? The statute is good enough
Nope, what was it, been modified at least 16 times in the past thirty years? (Someone give me the correct number please)
"So who cares about all of this blather about natural rights? It's the typical noise trying to create confusion"
Thanks to copyright extensions, no-one knows anymore what is copyrighted and what isn't. I've read posts here about people trying their hardest to stay legal, within the system, only to end up nowhere.
" For the most part, if you see someone's intellectual property and you make a copy for others like the file sharing people do, it's clearly infringement."
And of course with that absolute statement, you ignore situations like me sharing my copies of an MMO game with other players via P2P. The MMO game is "property" of the developer, they have copyright over it, and I'm making copies for others whenever I open up the launcher. So how is it infringement again?
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Who cares about natural rights? The statute is good enough
15 times in 30 years.
Copyright is anything but stable by the industry trying to expand it every two years.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Who cares about natural rights? The statute is good enough
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Who cares about natural rights? The statute is good enough
This is true only if you ignore the dramatic expansions over the past couple of decades.
They happen very frequently. Perhaps you just aren't looking in the right places. Look at the world of collage (particularly musical collage) and software development, to name two places where these obscure edge conditions are common.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Who cares about natural rights? The statute is good enough
Moreover, your argument that any file-sharing is automatically infringement is clearly incorrect. See, for example, the use of file-sharing by such companies as Microsoft and Blizzard to assist in patching games. Is that automatically infringement?
It is never as cut-and-dried as you think. Otherwise, the RIAA and their ilk would have unerring accuracy in finding actual infringements, which is rarely the case.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
"Who cares about natural rights?"
/Godwin
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Who cares about natural rights? The statute is good enough
That is why we have people suing for videos where they saw their "work" and I use that term loosely here is shown briefly on a TV set behind a baby dancing?
There are others suing others because they did work in public areas and are claiming ownership of that public area now for the purpose of image recording.
We see private collection agencies trying to collect from municipalities royalties because buskers are infringing some obscure interpretation of what is legal or not.
Yah right those things never happen enough.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Who cares about natural rights? The statute is good enough
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Who cares about natural rights? The statute is good enough
Why is Google processing 10 million infringement claims a month then?
And that is only one company can you imagine the real total if we add all the companies in any country?
That seems to fly directly in the face of that ridiculous assertions that the law have very well defined limits and it is obvious to everyone. For something so obvious it sure seems that either people don't see where those limits are and don't understand the law or people just don't give a fuck about that law.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Who cares about natural rights? The statute is good enough
Then the government was slow to enforce the law.
And?
That doesn't mean the law goes away or lapses.
Most of the the commentary here is devoid of logic and amounts to either tilting at windmills or willful blindness. Often both.
It isn't going to cause the end of copyright.
Seriously people, go do something productive with your life.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Who cares about natural rights? The statute is good enough
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Who cares about natural rights? The statute is good enough
Are you sure?
I can't see any copyright holder being able to pass the laws necessary to effectively "protect" that unnatural property.
Unlike a car a copyright work cannot be fenced or put in a safe place, unlike a car a copyright work cannot be monitored 24/7, unlike a car that have limited reach due to the laws of physics a copyright work have no physical attributes that can be secured, so unless people developed mind reading machines, very intrusive systems to monitor their entire population I am not seeing how copyright can ever survive in its current form, is not like people respect that law anyways, they don't not even the people responsible for producing those laws are capable of respecting it so for all intents and purposes copyright at the public level is long gone or I should say it was never there, on the commercial front though it is possible to enforce it since commercial entities are a government creation and they depend on the government to exist, people on the other hand have no such constraints and therefore are outside of the reach of their governments for the purposes of the law, even more so when they will not help enforce the law as written today against themselves.
Good luck trying to sell granted monopolies to the general population.
Just to prove the point, can you detect anybody, anywhere breaking the law?
I can detect individuals trying to steal a car? can you detect individuals stealing intellectual properties wherever that property is right now?
The obvious answer is no, you can't because unlike real property that has a limited physical space and can be monitored intellectual property cannot and therein lies the problem with the whole concept of intellectual property, for it to exist it must be imposed upon others and it must take away others rights, which will never be welcome by the people who has to give up their own rights and will never obey or fallow such laws.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Who cares about natural rights? The statute is good enough
It's nobody's problem if your enforcement of the law is shabby and useless enough that no one takes it seriously until you tread on the wrong toes. What the hell did they teach you in school? You were allowed to mess up as many times as possible, wreck everyone else's schoolwork until you got it right? Fuck off.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Who cares about natural rights? The statute is good enough
FTFY
it already has for me, and everyone else who uses the internet except a very vocal group of copyright loving artists (and trolls) who scream really loud and keep it alive with your whiny bribe voodoo
if it wasn't for that same voodoo copyright would have died decades ago ...kind of makes you zombies, and it's already the post-apocalypse, you know what THAT means
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re: Re: Re: Who cares about natural rights? The statute is good enough
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Although he had the third comment in, but he still showed up with his lawyerly talk and whatnot.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re:
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Re:
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
but they both tried to re write history to suit there needs....
and they both love censorship....
and terror....
and act like as-screw it they are Nazis.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re:
Heil MAFIAA!
yea, i like the sound of that
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Every plagiarist is and owner, every copycat its an owner of his own work which he copied from somewhere applying work.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
FUCK YOU AND DIE RIAA !!!
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Feist
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
As an aside, Donaldson did guide Wheaton v. Peters, but note that a number of elite legal writers in the nineteenth-century U.S. were terrifically fond of quoting Lord Mansfield and the justices of Millar to support a sort of Lockean natural rights justification for copyright as property.
However, many of these writers failed to acknowledge that Lord Mansfield was overturned in Donaldson. For one influential nineteenth-century example of this sort of revisionist legal scholarship, see Eaton S. Drone, Treatise on the Law of Property in Intellectual Productions (1879) 20-26.
Reading the the above comments, it's obvious that the semester is over.
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Wait a minute...
Did the RIAA just argue for communism?
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
Re: Wait a minute...
and corporate welfare
[ link to this | view in chronology ]
I kind of like some of their arguments on labor
[ link to this | view in chronology ]